Is Reality Real
Food for thought . This article is from the current issue of New Scientist. See how western scientists find it difficult to drop the concept of reality.
Is reality real? How
evolution blinds us to the truth about the world
We assume our senses see
reality as it is - but that could be just an evolved illusion obscuring the
true workings of quantum theory and consciousness.
By Donald Hoffman
LIFE insurance
is a bet on objective reality – a bet that something exists, even if I cease
to. This bet seems quite safe to most of us. Life insurance is, accordingly, a
lucrative business.
While we are alive and paying premiums, our conscious
experiences constitute a different kind of reality, a subjective reality.
My experience of a pounding migraine is certainly real to me, but it wouldn’t
exist if I didn’t. My visual experience of a red cherry fades to an experience
of grey when I shut my eyes. Objective reality, I presume, doesn’t likewise
fade to grey.
What is
the relationship between the world out there and my internal experience of it –
between objective and subjective reality? If I’m sober, and don’t suspect a
prank, I’m inclined to believe that when I see a cherry, there is a real cherry
whose shape and colour match my experience, and which continues to exist when I
look away.
This
assumption is central to how we think about ourselves and the world. But is it
valid? Experiments my collaborators and I have performed to test the form of
sensory perception that evolution has given us suggest a startling conclusion:
it isn’t. It leads to a crazy-sounding conclusion, that we may all be gripped
by a collective delusion about the nature of the material world. If that is
correct, it could have ramifications across the breadth of science – from how
consciousness arises to the nature of quantum weirdness to the shape of a
future “theory of everything”. Reality may never seem the same again.
The idea
that what we perceive might differ from objective reality dates back millennia.
Ancient Greek philosopher Plato proposed that we are like prisoners shackled in
a fire-lit cave. The action of reality is happening out of sight behind us, and
we see only a flickering shadow of it projected onto the cave wall.
Modern science largely abandoned such speculation. For
centuries, we have made stunning progress by assuming that physical objects,
and the space and time in which they move, are objectively real. This
assumption underlies scientific theories from Newtonian mechanics to Albert
Einstein’s relativity to Charles Darwin’s theory
of evolution by natural selection.
Natural selection, you might think, gives a simple reason why
our senses must get it largely right about objective reality. Those of our
predecessors who saw more accurately were more successful at performing
essential tasks necessary for survival, such as feeding, fighting, fleeing and
mating. They were more likely to pass on their genes, which coded for more
accurate perceptions. Evolution will naturally select for senses that give us a
truer view of the world. As the evolutionary theorist Robert
Trivers puts
it: “Our sense organs have evolved to give us a marvellously
detailed and accurate view of the outside world.”
“For
centuries we have made stunning progress by assuming things are real”
The truth of such statements can be tested with mathematical
rigour using the tools of evolutionary game
theory, introduced in the 1970s by John Maynard Smith. In this theory,
different strategies for coping with the natural world can be set against each
other in simulations to see which approaches are fitter – in the sense of
producing more offspring.
In the
case of perception, we can study how “truth” strategies, which see objective
reality as it is, fare against “pay-off” strategies, which see only survival
value. Take oxygen. Too much or too little oxygen in the air kills us; a narrow
range keeps us alive. Now imagine living in an environment where the level of
oxygen varies considerably, and you have to make survival judgements about
whether to venture outside.
For the
sake of this example, the amount of oxygen in the air is taken to be an
objective truth. You might imagine seeing it on a colour scale from red for low
to green for high. That’s the truth strategy: you know the truth, but you don’t
know if you’ll die. A pay-off strategy would mean seeing red colours for levels
of oxygen that kill you, and green for those that don’t. You see what you need
to survive, but don’t see the objective truth of how much oxygen there is.
The objective truth I started seeing a decade ago, in simulations
conducted together with my graduate students Justin
Mark and Brian Marion at the University of California, Irvine, is that evolution
ruthlessly selects against truth strategies and for pay-off strategies. An
organism that sees objective reality is always less fit than an organism of
equal complexity that sees fitness pay-offs. Seeing objective reality will make
you extinct.
If this
seems hard to swallow, suppose you are writing a novel on a laptop, and the
novel’s icon on the desktop is green, rectangular and in the centre of the
screen. Does this mean that the novel itself is green, rectangular and in the
centre of your laptop?
Of course
not. The desktop interface is there to mask a complex reality of software,
circuits and digital 1s and 0s to provide a simple way to interact with it. If
you actually had to flip computer bits to write a novel, you would switch to
pen and paper.
Reality is virtual
That,
evolutionary game theory predicts, is what evolution has done for us. Natural
selection has given us sensory systems that are a simplifying user interface
for the complexity of the world. Space, as we perceive it around us, is a 3D
computer desktop, with tables, chairs, the moon and mountains icons within it.
In other words, our senses constitute a virtual reality. If you
play the video game Grand Theft Auto with a
virtual-reality add-on, you see a 3D world with 3D objects, such as a black
steering wheel in front of you. If you turn your head, however, the steering
wheel disappears. Indeed, it ceases to exist, because it only exists when we
are looking where it should be in the simulation. The reality that exists –
circuits and software again – is utterly unlike a steering wheel. But it
prompts you to create a steering wheel when it is needed, and to destroy it
when it isn’t.
Our senses tell us only
what we need to know to survive
plainpicture/Rudi
Sebastian
In like
manner, we create an apple when we look, and destroy it when we look away.
Something exists when we don’t look, but it isn’t an apple, and is probably
nothing like an apple. The human perception of an apple is a data structure
that indicates something edible (a fitness pay-off) and how to eat it. We
create these data structures with a glance, and erase them with a blink.
Physical objects, and indeed the space and time they exist in, are evolution’s
way of presenting fitness pay-offs in a compact and usable form.
But hang
on, drop the apple. A lion on the African savannah isn’t just an icon in your
interface. It has agency, and can kill you, so it must be objectively real.
I wouldn’t
mess with a lion, for the same reason I wouldn’t carelessly drag the green icon
of my novel to the virtual recycle bin. Not because I take that icon literally,
and think the novel is green and rectangular. But I do take that icon
seriously: if I drag it to the bin, I could lose all my work.
The
objection that a lion must be objectively real because anyone who looks over
there sees a lion that we can all agree looks like a lion – so it isn’t unique
to our subjective experience – isn’t a valid one, either. Humans agree about
what we see because we have all evolved a similar interface. The interfaces of
some other species, such as prey mammals, may have icons for lions that are
similar to ours, and that guide actions similar to ours, such as keeping far
away from them.
That leaves the fact that treating our observed, subjective
reality as objective reality has allowed us to create scientific theories –
frameworks that allow us to make
predictions about how the world works, and so are presumably
part of an objective reality that exists outside our heads. But here too there
are hints from deep within science itself that perception and reality don’t
match.
Quantum
theory is our best physical theory of fundamental reality. But with
its counter-intuitive effects of “spooky action at a distance” and the
perennial mystery of the dead-yet-alive
Schrödinger’s cat, it drives a coach and horses through
cherished ideas from our classical realm of experience: that objects have
definite values of the properties pertaining to them, that those properties
don’t depend on how they are observed, and that influences propagate no faster
than light.
This is
jolting if we assume that objects and their measurable properties are part of
an objective reality. But it is no surprise if we think of objects and their
properties as data structures created as needed to represent fitness pay-offs.
In this case, the values of properties will depend on when and how we create
them.
This approach aligns with the quantum-Bayesian
interpretation of quantum theory, or QBism, in which the
uncertainty inherent in quantum observations is all in the minds of the
observers. As three pioneers of QBism, Christopher Fuchs, David Mermin and Rüdiger
Schack have put it, “A
measurement does not, as the term unfortunately suggests, reveal a pre-existing
state of affairs. It is an action on the world by an agent that results in the
creation of an outcome – a new experience for that agent. ‘Intervention’ might
be a better term.”
If our
team’s evolutionary ideas are true, that might lend momentum to models of
quantum theory that see quantum states, and the mathematical and
interpretational structures around them, as “epistemic” – reflecting not
necessarily reality, but just our state of knowledge of it.
But it
goes further. Even perceptions as seemingly fundamental as space and time might
not actually be part of objective reality. That insight could inform our search
for theories that unite the two great theories at the heart of modern physics.
“Even
perceptions as fundamental as space and time might not be part of objective
reality”
For decades, we have tried and failed to reconcile quantum
theory with general
relativity, Einstein’s theory of gravity that dictates how the universe
works on large scales. At a very basic level, these theories fail to agree on
the nature of space and time.
General relativity demands that space-time, the four-dimensional
structure that space and time together form, is smooth and continuous, whereas
a quantum description requires a pixelated description. As the theoretical
physicist Nima Arkani-Hamed has said: “Almost
all of us believe that space-time doesn’t exist, that space-time is doomed, and
has to be replaced by some more primitive building blocks.” Admittedly, no one
yet knows what those might be – but our insights suggest the hunch they must be
replaced is right.
It isn’t just in physics where we may need to overhaul our ideas
about reality to make progress. Another is in solving the “hard
problem” of consciousness. This problem of how and why our
brains generate conscious experience remains intractable despite centuries of
thought. As biologist Thomas Huxley put it in 1869: “How it is that anything so
remarkable as a state of consciousness comes about as a result of irritating
nervous tissue, is just as unaccountable as the appearance of the djinn, when
Aladdin rubbed his lamp.”
The
brain-exciting technology of transcranial magnetic stimulation (TMS)
illustrates how little progress we have made. Suppose we place a TMS unit near
your scalp, on the right side of your head, near an area of the occipital
cortex called V4. We turn on the device, and its strong and focused magnetic
fields inhibit neural activity nearby. All colour drains away from the left
half of your visual world; you see only shades of grey. We turn off the device,
and the colour seeps back in.
Marina Loeb
Chocolate and vanilla
Neuroscience
has turned up hundreds of such correlations between patterns of neural activity
and specific conscious experiences. Most attempts to explain these correlations
assume that the neural activity causes, or somehow gives rise to them. But how,
precisely? What neural activity causes the taste of vanilla, and why doesn’t it
cause the taste of chocolate? In a network of interacting neurons, how exactly
do changes in voltage, or in the flow of sodium, potassium and calcium ions
through pores in neural membranes, create an individual conscious experience?
There are
no theories, and few plausible ideas. But if we are trying to find the answer
to the problem of conscious experience in the firing of neurons in space and
time, when those neurons themselves are just icons in a subjective interface,
perhaps that is no wonder.
So how can
we break through our subjective perception and find objective reality? I don’t
know. But my collaborators and I are currently trying to solve the hard problem
of consciousness by building a theory in which the underlying reality emerges
from a vast network of interacting conscious agents and their experiences. Our
space-time interface – together with shapes, colours and other sensory
properties – is as a visualisation tool that some agents, like us, use to
simplify and interact with this network.
Our
hypothesis, of course, is probably wrong. But the point of science is to be
precise, so we can find out precisely what is wrong with the idea. Our theory
of interacting conscious agents fails if its predictions don’t square with
well-tested results of classical physics, quantum theory, general relativity,
evolution by natural selection and so on in our space-time interface.
And the
argument turns on itself. We used the theory of evolution by natural selection
to discover that what we perceive isn’t objective reality, but an interface
with it. Now we realise that evolution itself may be just an interface
projection of deeper dynamics stemming from a network of conscious agents. The
goal ahead is to work out those dynamics in detail, and figure out how,
precisely, they map onto our space-time interface. This will allow us to make
empirical predictions testable by experiments within our subjective reality.
Science so
far has focused its search on this immediate reality. What it has found can
guide our theories and test our predictions as we try to look beyond it, to
find the nature of objective reality. Can we do it? Just like I take out life
insurance, I’m betting we can.