Main Logo

Sunday 29 November 2020

වෙනත් සත්භාවවේදයක ක්වොන්ටම් භෞතිකය

 වෙනත් සත්භාවවේදයක ක්වොන්ටම් භෞතිකය

 

මේ ලිපිය 2010 දී කෝනෙල් විශ්වවිද්‍යාලයේ සඟරාවක පළවූවකි. අවශ්‍ය අයකුට එය එහි කියවිය හැකි ය. මෙහි රූප සටහන් හා ගණිත සංකේත එක්කෝ පළ නොවේ නැත්නම් නිවැරදිව සඳහන් නො වෙ. මුල් ලිපිය කියවීමෙන් ඒ සියල්ල බලා ගත හැකි ය.

 

මෙහි කියැවෙන්නේ අංශුවක් දෙතැනක හෝ වැඩි තැනක සිටීම පිළිබඳ කතාවකි. අංශුවකට එක වර සිදුරු දෙකකින් යා හැකි බවත් එමගින් ද්විත්ව සිදුරු පරීක්‍ෂණය තේරුම් ගත හැකි බවත් කියැවෙයි. එහි දී චතුස්කෝටික න්‍යාය වැදගත් වන අයුරුද කියැවෙයි.

 

අද වන විට අංශුවක් දෙතැනක පිහිටීම බටහිර භෞතික විද්‍යාවේ පිළිගැනී අවසන් ය. එහෙත් එය ඊනියා යථාර්ථය යැයි මම නොකියමි. එය තවත් කතාවක් පමණකි.

 

මේ ලිපිය ගැන යමක් කිව යුතු නම් ජාත්‍යන්තර සඟරාවකට යා හැකි ය. මුහුණු පොතේ තම තම නැණ පමණින් පළ කරන අනම් මනම් නොසලකා හරින බව පමණක් සලකන්න.

 

 

arXiv:1006.4712v1 [physics.gen-ph] 24 Jun 2010

Quantum Physics in a different ontology

Nalin de Silva

Department of Mathematics, University of Kelaniya, Kelaniya, Sri Lanka

 

Abstract

It is shown that neither the wave picture nor the ordinary particle picture offers

a satisfactory explanation of the double-slit experiment. The Physicists who

have been successful in formulating theories in the Newtonian Paradigm with

its corresponding ontology find it difficult to interpret Quantum Physics which

deals with particles that are not sensory perceptible. A different interpretation

of Quantum Physics based in a different ontology is presented in what follows.

According to the new interpretation Quantum particles have different proper-

ties from those of Classical Newtonian particles. The interference patterns are

explained in terms of particles each of which passes through both slits.

 

1 INTRODUCTION

Planck introduced his ideas on quanta or packets of energy towards the end

of the nineteenth century. In that sense Quantum Physics is more than one

hundred years old. From the very beginning Quantum Physics came up with

strange phenomena that made the Physicists to disbelieve what they themselves

were proposing to understand the new features that were being observed.

The so-called double-slit experiment1 continues to baffle the Physicists who

are glued to twofold two valued logic that is behind the Newtonian paradigm. As

it was one of the most fundamental experiments that they could not understand

in Quantum Physics the Nobel Prize winning Physicist Richard Feynmann once

declared that no body understood Quantum Physics! This statement by Feyn-

mann makes one to delve into the meaning of understanding. In other words

one has to understand what is meant by understanding. However, it is clear

that if one is confined to an ontology based in twofold formal logic, and linear

thinking one would be confused by a statement such as understanding what is

meant by understanding. A decade ago the intellectuals who were only familiar

with linear thinking and not with cyclic thinking would have left deliberations

into such statements to whom they call mystics, as such statements did not

come within the “rational” way of thinking. However, in this paper we would

not attempt to understand what is meant by understanding.

 

The principle of superposition which was familiar to Classical Physicists as

well, has taken an entirely different meaning with respect to Quantum Physics.

 

The essence of the principle can be explained as follows. If x and y are two

solutions of what is called a linear differential equation then x + y is also a

solution of the same differential equation. This is a simpler version of what

is generally known as the principle of superposition. In Classical Physics two

magnets giving rise to two different magnetic fields would combine to give one

magnetic field, and a compass that is brought to the resulting magnetic field

would respond to the resulting field, and not to the field of any one of the mag-

nets. It has to be emphasised that a magnet is in only one state, corresponding

to the respective magnetic field and it is the two fields of the two magnets that

combine to give one field though one would not find a single magnet that gives

rise to the resultant field. We could describe this phenomenon as that of two or

more becoming one. However, in the Quantum world things are different, and

the principle of superposition has an unusual interpretation.

 

2 THE WAVE NATURE OF PARTICLES

In order to discuss the new interpretation of the principle of superposition we

first consider the so called double-slit experiment where a stream of electrons

(in general, particles or photons) is made to pass through two slits and then

to strike a screen. If both slits are open an interference pattern is observed on

the screen. Now in Quantum Physics it is said that particles such as electrons

posses wave properties and photons (light) exhibit particle properties in addition

to their respective “normal” properties. Interference patterns are supposed to

result from wave properties and according to the Physicists the wave theory

successfully explains the formation of such patterns in the case of a stream of

particles fired from a source to strike the screen after passing through the slits.

The Physicists would claim that the double-slit experiment demonstrates that

particles such as electrons do exhibit wave properties.

 

The double-slit experiment has been carried out with only one electron pass-

ing through the slits one at a time2 (electrons at very low intensities) instead of a

stream of particles released almost simultaneously to pass through the two slits.

Even at very low intensities interference patterns have been observed after suffi-

ciently large number of electrons had been fired from the source. The Physicists

have been puzzled by this phenomenon. In the case of several electrons passing

through the slits simultaneously it could be explained using the wave properties

of the particles, in other words resorting to the wave picture. Unfortunately in

the case of electrons being shot one at a time this explanation was not possible

as what was observed on the screen was not a faint interference pattern corre-

sponding to one electron but an electron striking the screen at a single point

on the screen. These points in sufficiently large numbers, corresponding to a

large number of electrons, finally gave rise to an interference pattern. The wave

nature is only a way of speaking, as even in the case of large number of particles

what is observed is a collection of points and not waves interfering with each

other.

 

The Physicists also believe that an electron as a particle could pass through

only one of the slits and a related question that has been asked is whether it was

possible to find out the slit through which an electron passes on its way to the

screen. Various mechanisms, including “capturing” the electron using Geiger

counters, have been tried to “detect the path” of the electron, and it has been

found that if the particular slit through which the electron passed was detected

then the interference patterns were washed out. In other words determining the

particle properties of the electron erased its wave properties. Bohr, who was

instrumental in formulating the Copenhagen interpretation3, was of the view

that one could observe either the particle properties or the wave properties

but not both, and the inability to observe both wave and particle properties

simultaneously came to be referred to as complementarity. The experiments

that attempted to determine the slit through which the electron passed were

known as which-way (welcherweg) experiments as they attempted to find the

way or the path of the particle from the source to the screen. The outcome

of these experiments made it clear that the which-way experiments washed out

the interference patterns. It was believed that at any given time the electrons

exhibited either the particle properties or wave properties but not both.

However, what the Physicists failed to recognize was that in the case of one

electron shot at a time there was no weak interference pattern observed on the

screen for each electron thus illustrating that a single electron did not exhibit

any wave properties. The electron strikes the screen at one point, and it is the

collection of a large number of such points or images on the screen that gave

the interference pattern. In the case of a stream of electrons fired to strike the

screen each electron would have met the screen at one point and the collection

of such points or images would have given rise to an “interference pattern”.

Thus we could say that the interference patterns are obtained not as a result of

the “wave nature” of electrons but due to the collectiveness of a large number

of electrons that strike the screen. The “wave nature” arises out of “particle”

properties and not due to “wave properties”. Afshar4 comes closer to this view

when he states “in other words, evidence for coherent wave-like behavior is not a

single particle property, but an ensemble or multi-particle property”. We are of

the opinion that in the double-slit experiments no wave properties are observed

contrary to what is generally believed. It is the particle properties that are

observed, though not necessarily those of ordinary classical particles.

 

As a case in point this does not mean that a particle in Quantum Physics has

a definite path from the source to the screen through one of the slits, as could

be expected in the case of classical particles. For a particle to have a path it

should posses both position and momentum simultaneously. A path at any point

(assuming that it is a continuous path without cusps and such other points)

should have a well defined tangent. In the case of a particle moving, the direction

of the velocity (and the momentum) of the particle at any given point defines the

unit tangent vector to its path. Conversely the tangent to the path at any point

defines the direction of the velocity and the momentum of the particle at that

point. However, according to the Uncertainty Principle, both the momentum

and the position of a particle cannot be determined simultaneously, and if the

position is known then the momentum cannot be determined. Without the

momentum the direction of the velocity of the particle and hence the tangent

vector cannot be known implying that a continuous curve is not traced by

a particle in space. On the other hand if the momentum of the particle is

known then only the direction and magnitude of the velocity (momentum) and

properties of other non conjugate observables such as spin of the particle are

known, without the position being known. Thus the particle can be everywhere,

with variable probabilities of finding the particle at different points, but at

each point the particle being moving in parallel directions with the same speed.

However, as will be explained later, this does not mean that we could observe

the particle everywhere.

 

In the light of the uncertainty principle it is futile to design experiments to

find out the path of a particle. The so-called which-way experiments have been

designed to detect the slit through which the particle moves, on the assumption

that the particle moves through one slit only. However, in effect there is no

path that the particle follows and it is not correct to say that the particle

passes through one of the slits. The which-way experiment actually stops the

particle from reaching the screen and hence there is no possibility of obtaining

any “interference pattern”. It is not a case of observing particle properties

destroying the wave properties of matter, but an instance of creating a situation

where the particle is either not allowed to strike the screen or to pass through

only one slit deliberately. In effect it is the particle properties exhibited at the

screen that are cut off.

 

What is important is to note that interference patterns are observed only if

both slits are kept open, and also if the particles are free to reach the screen. If

one slit is closed or obstacles are set up in the guise of which-way experiments or

otherwise, so as not to allow the particles to reach the screen then no interference

patterns are observed. The most important factor is the opening of the two slits.

In the case of which-way experiments as well, what is effectively done is to close

one of the slits as particles through that slit are not allowed to reach the screen.

With only one slit open while the other slit is effectively closed with the which-

way experiment apparatus, no interference patterns are observed.

 

The Physicists are obsessed with the idea that a particle can be only at one

position at a given time, backed by the ontology of day to day experience. While

this may be the experience with our sensory perceptible particles (objects) or

what we may call ordinary Newtonian classical objects such as billiard balls, it

need not be the case with Quantum particles. However, from the beginning of

Quantum Physics, it appears that the Physicists have been of the view that a

particle can be at one position at a given time whether it is being observed or

not. Hence they seem to have assumed that on its “journey to the screen from

the source” a particle could pass through only one of the slits. They have worked

on the assumption that even if both slits are open the particle passes through

only one of the slits but behaves differently to create interference patterns as

if the particle is “aware” that both slits are open. According to the view of

the Physicists if only one slit is open the particles having “known” that the

other slit is closed pass through the open slit and “decide” not to form any

interference patterns. It is clear that the explanation given by the Physicists

for the formation of interference patterns on the basis of the particle picture is

not satisfactory. We saw earlier that the explanation given in the wave picture

is also not satisfactory as a single electron fired from the source does not form a

faint interference pattern on the screen. If the particles behave like waves then

even a single particle should behave like a wave and produce a faint interference

pattern, having interfered with itself. What is emphasised here is that the

final interference pattern is not the sum of faint interference patterns due to

single particles, but an apparent pattern formed by a collection of images on

the screen due to the particles. There is no interference pattern as such but

only a collection of the points where the particles strike the screen, or of the

images formed by the particles that were able to reach the screen. The images

finally depend on the probability that a particle would be at a given position.

Before we proceed further a clarification has to be made on “seeing” a par-

ticle at a given position at a given time in respect of the double-slit experiment.

In this experiment we are concerned with particles released from a source with

a given momentum and given energy. As such according to the uncertainty

principle, nothing can be said definitely on the position of these particles, im-

mediately after they leave the source. It can only be said that there is a certain

probability that the particle would be found in a certain position. Thus the

particle is “everywhere” “until” it is “caught” at some position such as a slit or

a screen. Though we have used the word “until”, time is not defined as far as the

particle is concerned as it has a definite energy. It can only be said that there is

a certain probability that the particle could be “seen” at a given place at a given

time, with respect to the observer. The particle is not only everywhere but also

at “every instant”. Thus it is meaningless to say the particle is at a given slit at

a given time as neither time nor position is defined for the particle with respect

to itself. The particle would meet the screen at some position on the screen at

some time but “before” that it was everywhere and at every instant. A photon

that is supposed to “move along a straight line” should not be considered as

such, but being at all points along the straight line at “all times” “before” it

interacts with a screen or another particle.

 

The probability of an electron striking the screen at a given point with only

one slit open is not the same as that when both slits are open. Thus when

a large number of particles strike the screen, the different probabilities give

rise to different “patterns” which are essentially collection of points where the

particles meet the screen. The “interference patterns” observed when both slits

are open are replaced by “other patterns” when one of the slits is closed. The

“interference patterns” as well as the “other patterns” are the results of particle

properties, the difference being due to the number of slits that are open. If both

slits are closed there is no pattern at all as no particle would reach the screen

under such conditions. When one of the slits is open there is a probability that

the particle can be at the position where the slit is whereas when both slits are

open there is a probability that the particle could be at both the slits “before”

reaching the screen. When both slits are open, the particle is at both slits and

the position is not known while the momentum of the particle is not changed

and has the original value with which it was shot. However, when one of the slits

is blocked the particle is at the other slit implying that the momentum is not

known. These uncertainties of the momentum would carry different particles

to different places on the screen, while in the case when both slits are open it

is the uncertainties of position that make the particle to strike the screen at

different positions. The difference between the “interference patterns” and the

“other patterns” is due to this.           

 

3 EXPERIMENTS OF AFSHAR

Afshar5 has claimed that he was able to demonstrate that an electron or a pho-

ton would exhibit both particle and wave properties (Figure 1). He allowed

light to pass through two slits and to interact with a wire grid placed so that

the nodes were at the positions of zero probability of observing a photon. The

photons were not affected by the wire grid as the nodes were at the positions of

zero probability and at those positions there were no photons to interact with

the grid. The photons were then intercepted by a lens system that was able

to identify the slit through which any single photon had passed. According to

Afshar the nodes of the grid at the positions of zero probability indicated that

the wave properties of the photons were observable while the lens system in de-

tecting the slit through which the photon had passed demonstrated the particle

properties of the photons. However, in this experiment, assuming that the lens

Figure 1: The wire grid and the lens system of Afshra, and the corresponding images

observed. No interference patterns after the lenses and Afshra claims that the wire grid

demonstrates the wave property while the images correspond to the particle property.

(Courtesy Afshra)

system detects the slit through which the photon passed, what is observed is

again the particle properties of the photons. The wire grid with the nodes at

the position of zero probabilities does not interact with the photons, as there

are no photons at positions of zero probability to interact with the grid. No so

called waves are observed, as there is no screen for the particles to strike. Thus

the wire grid has no effect in this experiment and with or without such a grid

the lens system would behave the same way.

 

Let us consider what would happen if the wire grid is shifted forwards to-

wards the source, backwards towards the lens system or laterally. As the nodes

of the wire grid would be shifted from the positions of zero probability some

photons would strike the grid and they would not proceed towards the lens sys-

tem. Thus the number of photons that reach the lens system would be reduced

and there would be a decrease in intensity of light received at the lens. Though

Afshar claims that wave properties are observed just by placing a wire grid so

that its nodes are at the positions of zero probability, it is not so.

The so called wave properties could be observed only by placing a screen in

between the wire grid and the lens system. As we have mentioned above, even

then what is observed is a collection of images at the points where the photons

strike the screen, and not wave properties as such. In this case as all the photons

would have been absorbed by the screen, the lens system would not be able to

detect any photons nor the “slit through which the photons passed”. On the

other hand if the screen is kept beyond the lens system then there would not be

any photons to strike the screen and hence no “wave properties”.

 

4 EXPERIMENTS AT KELANIYA

We at the University of Kelaniya have given thought to this problem, and one

of my students Suraj Chandana has carried out a number of experiments, which

may be identified as extensions of the experiment of Afshar. Chandana and de

Silva6 had predicted that if we were to have a single slit and then a screen,

instead of the wire grid and the lens system, “after” the photons have passed

through the two slits, then the photons would pass through the single slit with

the same probability as that of finding a photon at the point where the slit was

kept. This implied that if the slit was kept at a point where the probability of

finding the photon is zero, the photon would not pass through the slit to strike

the screen, but on the other hand, if the slit was kept at any other point there was

a non zero probability that the photon would pass through the slit, and striking

the screen. Thus if a stream of photons is passed through two slits, and “then”

a single slit, “before” striking the screen, depending on the position of the single

slit the intensity with which the photons strike the screen would change. Further

it implies that these intensities should correspond to the intensities observed in

connection with the “interference patterns” observed in the case of the standard

double-slit experiment, if the positions of the slit were varied along a line parallel

(by moving the single slit along a line parallel to the double-slit and the screen)

to the double-slits and the screen. Chandana has been successful in obtaining

the results as predicted. In another experiment Chandana7 had an Aluminium

sheet of very small thickness joining the points or positions where the probability

of finding a photon is zero (positions of zero probability), stretching from the

double-slits to the screen as illustrated in the figure 2. As an obstacle placed at

a position of zero probability would not affect the photon the Aluminium sheet

had no effect on the visible interference patterns on the screen. This experiment

was carried out by Chandana with number of Aluminium sheets placed along

 

Figure 2: The figure represents the aluminium sheet joining the positions of zero

probability from a position closer to the double slit to the screen.

 

lines joining the positions of zero probability stretching from the double-slits

to the screen. We were not surprised to find that the Aluminium sheets did

not interfere with the interference patterns. However, even if one of the sheets

is slightly displaced the interference pattern is destroyed as the photons now

interact with the sheets at points where the probability of finding a photon is

not zero.

 

These observations are not consistent with the wave picture as a wave would

not be able to penetrate the Aluminium sheets without being affected. Even

the pilot waves of Bohm are not known to go through a material medium undis-

turbed. As we have argued a single electron emitted from the source would

not exhibit a faint interference pattern on the screen but a spot or an image

having passed beyond the slits. The Physicists are interested in the wave pic-

ture to explain the interference patterns as they find it difficult to believe that

a particle would pass through both slits simultaneously. Thus they mention of

particle properties when they are interested in “capturing” particles and of wave

properties in explaining phenomena such as the interference pattern.

 

5 PRINCIPLE OF SUPERPOSITION IN QUAN-

TUM PHYSICS

We consider the Quantum entities to be particles though of a nature different

from that of Classical Newtonian particles. We have no inhibition in believing

that the Quantum particles unlike the Newtonian particles could pass through

both slits at the “same time”, as the logic of different cultures permits us to do

so. Physics and in general Mathematics and sciences are based on Aristotelian

two valued twofold logic according to which a proposition and its negation can-

not be true at the same time. Thus if a particle is at the slit A, the proposition

that the particle is at A is true and its negation that the particle is not at A

is not true, and vice versa. Therefore if the particle is at A then it cannot be

anywhere else as well, and hence cannot be at B. This is based on what may

be called the Aristotelian- Newtonian - Einsteinian ontology where a particle

can occupy only one position at a given time in any frame of reference of an

observer. However, in fourfold logic (catuskoti) a proposition and its negation

can be both true, and hence in that logic it is not a contradiction to say that a

particle is at the slit A and at somewhere else (say at the slit B) at the “same

instant” or “every instant” Thus according to catuskoti the particle can be at

many places at the same time or at many instants with respect to the observer.

In the case of the double-slit experiment, the momentum of a particle is

known, as the particles are fired with known energy, and hence the position

is not known. In such a situation Heisenberg’s uncertainty principle demands

that the position of the particle is not known. The position of the particle is

relieved only after a measurement is made to determine the position. Before the

measurement, the particle is in a superposition of states corresponding to the po-

sitions in space the particle could be found. After the measurement the particle

would be found in a definite position (state), collapsing from the superposition

of a number of states to that of the definite state. Before the measurement

what could have been said was that there was a certain probability of finding

the particle at a given position. Though the particle is in a superposition of

states before a measurement is made to find the position, it is in a definite state

with respect to the momentum.

 

In Quantum Mechanics unlike in Classical Mechanics, a state of a system,

a particle or an object is represented by a vector in a Mathematical space

known as the Hilbert space. The observables such as position, momentum, and

spin are represented by what are known as Hermitian operators. If a system

is in a state represented by an eigenstate |_ > of a Hermitian operator A,

belonging to the eigenvalue a, then the system has the value a corresponding

to the observable represented by the Hermitian operator A. This is expressed

mathematically by A|_ >= a|_ >. If B is the conjugate operator of A, then the

value corresponding to the observable represented by B is not known. All that

can be said, according to the standard Copenhagen interpretation, is that if the

value corresponding to the observable represented by B is measured, then there

is a certain probability of obtaining an eigenvalue of B as the measurement.

Before the measurement is made nothing could be said of the value. In plain

language this means that if the value of a certain observable is known then the

value of the conjugate observable is not known.

 

However, the state |_ > can be expressed as a linear combination of the

eigenstates |        > of B in the form |_ >= P|ci             i > where ci 2 C, the field of

complex numbers. In other words the coefficients of |              >’s in the expansion

of |_ > are complex numbers. The Copenhagen interpretation tells us that

when the observable corresponding to B is measured it would result in a state

corresponding to one of the |          >’s with the measurement yielding the eigenvalue

b to which the particular | > belongs, the probability of obtaining the value b

being given by the value of the relevant |c|2. Before the measurement is made

nothing can be said regarding the observable corresponding to B. According

to Bohr, it is meaningless to talk of the state of the system with respect to B

as nothing could be observed. There is no knowledge regarding the observable

corresponding to B as it has not been observed. The value or the knowledge

of the observable is “created” by the observer who sets up an experiment to

measure the value in respect of B. The observed depends on the observer and

it makes no sense to talk of an observable unless it has been observed. This

interpretation is rooted in positivism as opposed to realism in which the entire

corpus of knowledge in Newtonian - Einsteinian Physics is based. This body of

knowledge is also based in Aristotelian - Newtonian - Einsteinian ontology.

As a particular case one could refer to the conjugate Hermitian operators

in respect of position and momentum of a particle in Quantum Mechanics.

When the position of a particle is measured then its momentum is not known.

According to the Copenhagen Interpretation, it can only be said that if an

apparatus is set up to measure the momentum, the observer would observe one

of the possible values for the momentum and that there is a certain probability

of observing the particular value. Before the measurement is made the particle

has no momentum, as such, and it is meaningless to talk of the momentum of

the particle. The observer by his act of observation gives or creates a value for

the momentum of the particle, so to speak of. Once the momentum is measured

the observer has knowledge of the momentum but not before it. However, after

the momentum is measured, the knowledge of the position of the particle is

“washed off” and hence it becomes meaningless to talk of the position of the

particle. The observer could have knowledge only of either the momentum or

the position, but not of both. A version of this conclusion is sometimes referred

to as the uncertainty principle.         

 

What we have been discussing in the proceeding paragraphs is the principle

of superposition. A particle or a system with its position known is represented by

a vector |_ >in Hilbert space, which is an eigenvector of the Hermitian operator

A corresponding to the position. When the position of the particle or the

system is known, the momentum is not known. If B is the Hermitian operator

corresponding to the momentum, then |_ > is not an eigenvector of B. However,

|_ > can be expressed as a linear combination of the eigenvectors |      >’s of B

though the momentum is not observed. The superposition of the |       >’s cannot

be observed, and neither can be resolved into observable constituent parts. This

is different from the principle of superposition in Classical Physics, where the

resultant can be resolved into its constituent parts.

 

For example as we have mentioned in the introduction the resultant magnetic

field due to two magnets can be resolved into its two components and can be

observed. One of the magnets can be taken off leaving only one of the constituent

magnetic fields. The superposition is there to be observed and if the magnet

that was taken off is brought back to its original position the resultant magnetic

field reappears. In Quantum Physics the superposition cannot be observed

without disturbing the system and when it is disturbed to measure the conjugate

variable, only one of the states in the superposition could be observed and we

would not have known in advance if that particular state were to appear as a

result of the disturbance induced by us.

 

6 COPENHAGEN INTERPRETATION

In Classical Physics, as we have already stated, superposition is there to be

observed. However, in Quantum Physics the superposition cannot be observed,

and further unlike in Classical Physics interpretations are required to “translate”

the abstract Mathematical apparatus and concepts into day to day language.

In Classical Physics one knows what is meant by the position or the momen-

tum of a particle and those concepts can be observed and understood without

an intermediate interpretation. However, in Quantum Physics, the state of a

particle or a system is represented by a vector in Hilbert space and observables

are represented by Hermitian operators in Hilbert space. An interpretation or

interpretations are needed to express these and other concepts to build a con-

crete picture out of the abstract apparatus. Copenhagen interpretation is one

such interpretation and it is the standard interpretation as far as most of the

Physicists are concerned.

 

Bohr more than anybody else was instrumental in formulating the Copen-

hagen interpretation, and he in turn was influenced by positivism and Chinese

Ying - Yang Philosophy. As a positivist he believed that only the sensory per-

ceptible phenomena exist and did not believe in the existence of that could

not be “observed”. When a state of a particle or system is represented by an

eigenvector of an observable (Hermitian operator in Hilbert space) the corre-

sponding value of the observable can be measured and the positivist school had

no problem in accepting the existence of such state. For example if the mo-

mentum of a particle is known then the state of the particle is represented by

a certain vector in Hilbert space, belonging to the particular eigenvalue that

has been measured. However, the problem arises when the conjugate Hermitian

operator, in this case the position, is considered, as in positivism the ontology

is connected with observations and sensory perceptions. We are not considering

logical positivism and there seems to be no interpretation of Quantum Physics

in a logical positivist ontology.

 

As we have seen a given eigenstate of a Hermitian operator that has been

observed can be expressed as a linear combination of the eigenstates of the

conjugate operator. To a positivist, though the given eigenstate exists as it is

observed, the eigenstates of the conjugate operator are not observable and it is

meaningless for him to talk of such states. Thus if the momentum of a particle

has been measured, the eigenstates belonging to the eigenvalues of the conjugate

operator, which is the position, are not observed and the positivist would not

say anything regarding the existence of such states. As far as the positivist is

concerned, there is only a probability of finding the particle at some position,

and the particle will be at some position only after the relevant measurement is

carried out.

 

In the case of the double-slit experiment, this means that a positivist would

not say whether the particle passes through a particular slit as it is not ob-

served. However he assumes that it it is at one of the slits and not at both as

the Aristotelian - Newtonian - Einsteinian ontology demands that the particle

should be at one of the slits and not at both slits. (The positivists share with the

realists the Aristotelian - Newtonian - Einsteinian ontology. They differ from

the realists when they insist that nothing could be said of non observables.) If

a measurement is made, that is if an experiment is carried out to find out the

slit where the particle is, then the particle would be found at one of the slits

washing out the “interference pattern”. Then superposition is collapsed and

“decoherance” sets in resulting “chaotic pattern”.

 

A realist differs from a positivist in that the former would want to know the

slit at which the particle is (the slit through which the “particle passes”) even

without observing it. He would say the particle would pass through one of the

slits whether one observes it or not, and that it is an integral property of the

particle independent of the observer. The Classical Physicists were realists. An

object in Classical Physics has a momentum whether it is measured or not. The

observer in Classical Physics measures the momentum that the particle already

possesses. In Quantum Physics the positivists would say that the particle has

no momentum before it is measured but acquires a momentum as a result of

the measurement.

 

We would not go into further details on the differences between the realist

position and the positivist position. However, what is relevant to us is that both

the realist and the positivist would agree that the particle “goes through one

slit”, meaning that at a “given time” the particle is found only at one of the slits.

They would also agree on the wave nature of the particles. They have to depend

on the wave nature as they assume that the particle passes through only one

slit, and as such they would not be able to explain the “interference patterns”

without the wave properties of the particles, as particles “passing through” only

one slit would not produce “interference patterns”.

 

7 A NEW INTERPRETATION

We differ from the positivists as well as the realists since we believe that the

particle is found at both slits and hence “pass through both” in the common

parlance. In general we include the postulate that the eigenstates |      >’s in

|_ >= P|ci              i > exist in addition to |_ > (Postulate 3 below). We have also

introduced the concept of a mode. A mode of a particle or a system is essentially

a potential observable. A mode has the potential to be observed though it may

not be observed at a particular instant. For example, position, momentum, spin

are modes. A particle or a system can be in both modes corresponding to two

conjugate Hermitian operators, though only one mode may be observed.

A revised version of the postulates of the new interpretation formulated by

Chandana and de Silva9 is given below.

 

1. A state of a Quantum Mechanical system is represented by a vector (ray) _

in the Hilbert space, where _ can be expressed as different linear combina-

tions of the eigenvectors in the Hilbert space, of Hermitian operators, any

operator corresponding to a mode. In other words a state of a Quantum

Mechanical system can be represented by different linear combinations of

eigenvectors of different modes, each linear combination being that of the

eigenvectors of one of the modes. Thus a state could have a number of

modes, each mode being a potential observable.

 

2. If _ is expressed as a linear combination of two or more eigenvectors of a

Hermitian operator, that is a mode, then the corresponding mode cannot

be observed (or measured) by a human observer with or without the aid

of an apparatus. In other words the particular mode cannot be observed

and a value cannot be given to the observable, which also means that no

measurement has been made on the observable.

 

3. However, the non observation of a mode does not mean that the mode does

not “exist”. We make a distinction between the “existence” of a mode, and

the observation of a mode with or without the aid of an apparatus. A mode

corresponding to a given Hermitian operator could “exist” without being

observed. The knowledge of the “existence” of a mode is independent

of its observation or measurement. In other words the knowledge of the

“existence” of a mode of a Quantum Mechanical state is different from the

knowledge of the value that the observable corresponding to the relevant

Hermitian operator would take.

 

4. If a mode of a Quantum Mechanical state is represented by a single eigen-

vector, and not by a linear combination of two or more eigenvectors, of a

Hermitian operator, then the mode could be observed by a human observer

with or without the aid of an apparatus, and the value of the correspond-

ing observable (or the measured value) is given by the eigenvalue which

the eigenvector belongs to. It has to be emphasised that only those modes

of a Quantum Mechanical state, each represented by a single eigenvector,

and not by a linear combination of eigenvectors, of an Hermitian operator

can be observed at a given instant.

 

5. If a mode of a Quantum Mechanical state is represented by an eigenvector

of a Hermitian operator then the mode corresponding to the conjugate

operator cannot be represented by an eigenvector of the conjugate Her-

mitian operator. It can be expressed as a linear combination of two or

more of the eigenvectors of the conjugate operator. This means that the

mode corresponding to the conjugate operator cannot be observed, or in

other words it cannot be measured. However, the relevant mode “exists”

though it cannot be observed.

 

6. It is not necessary that at least one of the modes corresponding to two

conjugate operators should be represented by a single eigenvector of the

relevant operator. It is possible that each mode is represented by linear

combinations of two or more eigenvectors of the corresponding operator.

In such situations neither of the modes could be observed.

 

7. A state of a Quantum Mechanical system can be altered by making an

operation that changes a mode or modes of the state. However, not all

operations correspond to measurements or observations. Only those oper-

ations that would result in a mode being expressed as a single eigenvector,

and not as a linear combination of the eigenvectors of an operator would

result in measurements.

 

8. A particle entangled with one or more other particles is in general repre-

sented by a linear combination of eigenvectors of an Hermitian operator

with respect to a mode, while the whole system of particles is in general

represented by a linear combination of the Cartesian products of the eigen-

vectors. In the case of two particles it takes the form Pcij |_i > |_j >. If

one of the particles is in a mode that is observed, then the particles entan-

gled with it are also in the same mode as an observable. If a measurement

is made on some other mode then instantaneously, the corresponding val-

ues in the same mode of the entangled particles are also determined. In

such case, for two particles the whole system is represented by vectors of

the form |_i > |_j >. If the number of entangled particles is less than the

dimension of the space of the eigenvectors of the Hermitian operator, then

if a measurement is made in the particular mode, the particle would be

represented by one of the eigenvectors, while the other particles entangled

with it would be each represented by a different eigenvector of the Her-

mitian operator. However, if the number of entangled particles is greater

than the dimension of the space of the eigenvectors, then in some cases,

more than one particle would be represented by a given eigenvector.

According to this interpretation if the momentum of a particle is known then

it has not one position but several positions. In other words the particle can

be at number of positions in superposition though we are not able to observe

it at any one of those positions. The particle could be observed only if it is at

one position. If an experiment is carried out to determine the position of the

particle the superposition or the wave function would collapse, and the particle

would be located at one of the positions where it was before the measurement

was made.

 

Similarly if the particle is in the position mode that is observed then it can

have several momenta in superposition but we would not be able to observe any

one of them. If we perform an experiment to determine the momentum, that

is if a measurement is made, then the superposition of momenta would collapse

to one of them, enabling us to determine the value of the momentum.

With respect to the double-slit experiment this implies that the particle

is at both slits in superposition without being observed and if we perform an

experiment to determine the slit “through which the particle passes” (the slit

where the particle is) then the superposition collapses and the particle would

be found only at one of the positions. The positivists while assuming that

the particle “passes through only one slit” would not say anything on the slit

“through which the particle passes” as it cannot be observed. For the positivist

it is meaningless to speculate on something that cannot be observed. The realists

too assume that the particle “passes through” only one slit but would not be

satisfied with the positivist position, and claim that a theory that is not able to

determine the slit through which the particle passes is incomplete.

We make a distinction between being in existence and being observed. A

particle or a system can exist in a certain mode without being observed. In this

case the state of the particle or the state is expressed as a linear combination

or superposition of the eigenstates of the relevant Hermitian operator and the

particle or the system exists in all the relevant eigenstates without being ob-

served. The mode is observed only when the state of the particle or the system

is expressed as a single eigenstate of the relevant Hermitian operator.

The existence of modes with more than one eigenstates has been known for

sometime. Monroe10 and his colleagues in 1996 were able to demonstrate the

existence of two spin states of Beryllium cation simultaneously however without

observing them. One could say that the interference obtained by them could

be understood on the basis of the existence of simultaneous spin states of the

Beryllium cation. Since then similar experiments have been carried out and the

existence of superposition of eigenstates cannot be ruled out anymore.

 

8 A DIFFERENT ONTOLOGY AND LOGIC

In the ontology presented here no distinction is made of the existence of sensory

perceptible objects and of other entities. There is no absolute existence as such

and all existences are relative to the mind. It has been shown by de Silva11 that

even the mind could be considered as a creation of the mind a phenomenon

not in contradiction with cyclic thinking. It is the mind that creates concepts

including that of self, and as such sensory perceptible objects do not have any

preference over the others.

 

As we have mentioned the positivists find it difficult to take cognizance of

entities that are not sensory perceptible and it is this ontology that makes them

not to commit on the existence of unobserved “objects”. In the present ontology

all existences are only conventional and not absolute as such. Thus the existence

of simultaneous eigenstates or superposition of eigenstates is not ruled out in

the present ontology. We have no inhibition to postulate the existence of such

states and it is not in contradiction with catuskoti or fourfold logic that may be

identified as the logic of the ontology presented here.

 

As Jayatilleke12 has shown in fourfold logic or sometimes referred to as tetra

lemma, unlike in twofold logic a proposition and its negation can be both true

and false. (However, we do not agree with the interpretation of fourfold logic

given by Jayatilleke.). In twofold logic if a proposition is true then its negation

is false, and if a proposition is false, then its negation is true. In addition to

these two cases fourfold logic has two more cases where both the proposition and

its negation can be true or both false. Thus the proposition that a particle is at

A, and the proposition that a particle is not at A, can be both true in fourfold

logic. (According to fourfold logic the case could arise where the particle may

be neither at A nor not at A.) We may deduce from that a particle can be

both at A and B (not at A) at the “same time”. In other words a particle

can be at both slits in respect of the double-slit experiment, and in general a

mode represented by a superposition of two or more eigenvectors can exist as

the particle or the system can be at number of “positions” simultaneously in

fourfold logic.

 

In twofold Aristotelian logic a particle has to be either at A or not at A. Thus

the Physicists whether they are realists or positivists find it difficult to accept

that a particle can “pass through both slits” simultaneously, and they have to

resort to so called wave nature in order to explain the interference patterns.

 

9 DISCUSSION

It is seen that both wave picture and the ordinary particle picture fail to explain

the interference patterns observed in the double-slit experiment. The wave

picture fails as a weak intensity stream of electrons (one electron at a time)

exhibits no interference patterns in the case of few electrons. The ordinary

particle picture fails as a particle passing through only one slit would not produce

interference patterns. The Physicists had to resort to the wave picture as the

logic in either positivism or realism would not permit a particle to pass through

both slits.

 

In the case of the experiments conducted by Chandana then at the Univer-

sity of Kelaniya, Sri Lanka, the wave picture as well as the classical particle

picture come across more problems as neither a wave nor an ordinary particle

would be able to penetrate the aluminium sheets without being affected. These

experiments justify our new interpretation involving modes of the particle or

the system and the particle picture presented here where a particle can be at

both slits. In general we postulate that a particle or system can exist in a mode

where more than one eigenstates are in a superposition. The position where

a particle is found depends only on the relevant probability, and the so-called

interference patterns are only collections of images formed by such particles

striking the screen at different positions with the relevant probabilities.

The new postulates are consistent with the ontology where the “existence”

of a particle or an object does not necessarily mean that it could be observed or

that it is sensory perceptible in general, and the fourfold logic. It appears that,

unlike Classical Physics with its twofold logic and realist ontology, Quantum

Physics is rooted not even in a “positivist ontology” but in a different ontology

and fourfold logic and we should be able to develop new concepts in Quantum

Physics, especially regarding the motion of a Quantum particle from a point A

to another point B. It is not known how a particle “moves” from the double-slit

to the screen in the experiments carried out by Chandana, nor how a particle

with less energy than the value of a potential barrier “scales the walls”. In the

latter case all that the Physicists have done is to come up with concepts such

as “tunnel effect”. It may be that it is neither the particle that left the point

A nor some other particle that reaches the point B, if we are to make use of

the fourth case of fourfold logic. Chandana in his M.Phil. thesis submitted to

the University Kelaniya in September 2008 has described few more experiments

that agree with the present ontology and fourfold logic.

 

References

1. Bagget Jim, 1997. The Meaning of Quantum Theory, Oxford University Press.

2. Afshar, S.S., 2005. Sharp complementary wave and particle behaviours in the

same welcherweg experiment, Proc. SPIE 5866, 229-244.

3. Bagget Jim, 1997. The Meaning of Quantum Theory, Oxford University Press.

4. Afshar, S.S., 2005. Sharp complementary wave and particle behaviours in the

same welcherweg experiment, Proc. SPIE 5866, 229-244.

5. Afshar, S.S., 2005. Sharp complementary wave and particle behaviours in the

same welcherweg experiment, Proc. SPIE 5866, 229-244.

6. Chandana S. and de Silva Nalin, 2004. On the double-slit experiment, Annual

Research Symposium, University of Kelaniya, 57-58.

7. Chandana S. and de Silva Nalin, 2007. Some experiments involving double-slits,

Annual Research Symposium, University of Kelaniya,133-134.

8. Bohm D, 1980. Wholeness and the implicate order, Routledge, London.

9. Chandana S. and de Silva Nalin, 2004. A new interpretation of Quantum Mechanics,

Annual Research Symposium, University of Kelaniya, 59-60.

10. Monroe C., Meekhof D. M., King B. E., Wineland D. J., 1996. A “Schr¨odinger

Cat” Superposition State of an Atom, Science, 272, 1132.

11. de Silva Nalin, Sinhala Bauddha Manasa www.kalaya.org/files/nps/070405.pdf.

12. Jayatilleke, K. N.,1963. Early Buddhist Theory of Knowledge, Motilal Banarsidass.