න්යාය හා පරස්පර
2023 ජනවාරි
14 නිව්
සයන්ටිස්ට්
සඟරාව
වෙන්
වී
ඇත්තේ
දැනුමේ
සීමා
(Limits of Knowledge) සඳහා.
ඒ
සම්බන්ධ
ලිපි
පහක්
පළ
වී
තිබෙනවා.
අප
ඊයේ
එක්
ලිපියක්
පළ
කළා.
අද
න්යාය
(Logic) ගැන
වූ
ලිපියක්.
මෙයත් මෙරට දර්ශනය හදාරන්නන්ට වැදගත් වනවාට සැකයක් නැහැ. මා දන්නවා කැලණිය විශ්වවිද්යාලයේ දර්ශන අධ්යනංශයේ න්යාය හා විරුද්ධාභාස (Paradoxes) ගැන උනන්දුවක් දක්වන අය ඉන්න බව. අවශ්ය අයට ආචාර්ය ධරණීතගේ ආචාර්ය උපාධි නිබන්ධනය පරිශීලනය කරන්න පුළුවන්. සංජීවනී රුපසිංහ මහත්මිය විරුද්ධාභාස ගැන අධ්යයනය කරනවා.
Logic
underpins knowledge – but what if logic itself is flawed?
We use
logic to build facts into systems of thought, but paradoxes force us to
question what we think we know. And it could be worse, because logic may not be
sufficient to comprehend reality
MIND 10
January 2023
By Abigail
Beall
I AM not
bald. At least, not as I write this. Yet if a malevolent philosopher were to
pluck the hairs out of my head, one by one, I would end up bald. But how many
would have to be removed before I went from having a lustrous head of hair to
being bald? It is tricky, if not impossible, to say. And if we can’t identify
the transition to baldness, am I actually bald at all?
This is a
version of a thought experiment favoured by philosophers, first described with
reference to grains of sand in a heap, called the sorites paradox (from the
Greek word for “heap”). It is often used as evidence that classical logic might
be insufficient to describe the world around us.
That is
troubling because, though we don’t pay it much attention, logic runs through
human knowledge as if it were a stick of rock. We assume that we can build up a
sequence of facts into systems of thought. But if logic itself is lacking,
where does that leave us?
This article
is part of a special series on the limits of knowledge, in which we explore:
How can we
understand quantum reality if it is impossible to measure?
How AI is
shifting the limits of knowledge imposed by complexity
Why maths,
our best tool to describe the universe, may be fallible
Why some
aspects of physical reality must be experienced to be known
Paradoxes
start with a premise that seems true, apply reasoning that also seems valid,
but end up at a false or contradictory conclusion. As a result, many paradoxes
force us to question what we think we know. They come in different varieties,
some more difficult to explain away than others. One of the most confounding
takes the form of a simple sentence (see “Will we ever solve the liar
paradox?”, below).
The back of
a bald head, painted with a rainbow symbol
‘Baldness’
turns out to be a slippery concept
One
solution to the sorites paradox is to admit that terms are sometimes too vague
to be useful outside of everyday conversation. But some philosophers argue that
logic itself needs a refresh. One approach is to say that there are different
degrees of truth. Take the case of my hair removal. Halfway through the process
of plucking, I am still not bald, but I am less “not bald” than I was at the
start. Fuzzy logic, a kind of computing using degrees of truth rather than 1s
and 0s, was introduced by computer scientist Lotfi Zadeh in 1965. It is still
used in some artificial intelligence systems today, like IBM’s Watson.
Supervaluationism
Another
approach, called supervaluationism, provides a way to discuss vague concepts by
categorising some statements as “true” and others as “supertrue”. Imagine a
minor character in a story, for example. If we aren’t told how many siblings
they have, we can say that it isn’t supertrue that they have three siblings. It
is true, however, as long as there is no information in the story to tell us
otherwise. “The bold claim is that truth – ordinary truth – really is
supertruth, and falsity is superfalsity,” says philosopher Brian Weatherson at
the University of Michigan.
But there
is a deeper question here: can we be sure that logic, even a reformed kind, is
enough to understand the universe in all its fullness?
It is a
question that David Wolpert at the Santa Fe Institute in New Mexico has been
thinking about for decades. In a recent monograph, he spelled out his argument
that it is more likely than not that there is some higher mode of logic that
could be used to understand the universe, but that human minds wouldn’t be able
to grasp.
Read more:
A new kind of logic: How to upgrade the way we think
Just think
of that humble linguistic device, the question. Wolpert says there are
creatures – things like a single-celled paramecium – that couldn’t conceive of
the idea of a question. In fact, according to our standards of intelligence,
every other species on Earth is limited in some regard in the way it
understands the world around it. Why should we be any different? “We are the
paramecia,” says Wolpert. “What is beyond us?”
Wolpert
thinks there are ways we could potentially get at higher systems of thought
that go beyond logic as we know it. Perhaps it will be a super Turing machine
that can transcend the normal rules of computing or an intelligent form of
extraterrestrial life that shares its wisdom with us. Perhaps it will be
something different altogether. And what will this new plane of understanding
be like? “I can’t conceive of it,” says Wolpert. “But that’s the whole point.”
New
Scientist audio
You can now
listen to many articles – look for the headphones icon in our app newscientist.com/app
WILL WE
EVER SOLVE THE LIAR PARADOX?
What are we
to make of the sentence “This sentence is false”? If we say the sentence is
true, then it is false. If we say it is false, then it is true. Whichever we
choose, there is a violation of a common-sense rule: declarative sentences
ought to be either true or false, not both. This kind of paradox rarely crops
up in everyday life, of course, and some have suggested that we can avoid
problems by having better linguistic rules that exclude paradoxes.
But there
are other ways to respond to this puzzle, says Margaret Cuonzo, a philosopher
at Long Island University in New York. “One is to say that our logic needs to
be revised to handle more complex phenomena.” This is the route a few
philosophers have taken. For instance, an approach called dialetheism says that
some things can be true and false at the same time. But this gets complicated.
Proponents of dialetheism have to figure out “how claiming something can be
true and false doesn’t lead to a system in which you can prove anything”, says
Cuonzo. If things can be true and false, facts start to lose meaning. This is
one paradox that remains deeply challenging to explain away.